17 April 2015
16 April 2015
ARTICLE ANNOUNCEMENT: Presumption of Innocence or Presumption of Mercy?: Weighing Two Western Modes of Justice James Q. Whitman
By James Q. Whitman
American criminal law has a deep commitment to the presumption of innocence. Yet at the same time, American criminal justice is, by international standards, extraordinarily harsh. This Article addresses this troubling state of affairs. The Article contrasts the American approach with the approach of the inquisitorial tradition of continental Europe. Inquisitorial justice, it argues, has a less far-reaching presumption of innocence than American justice does. Yet if continental justice puts less weight on the rights of the innocent it puts more on the rights of the guilty: While its presumption of innocence is comparatively weaker, it has what can be called a strong presumption of mercy. The continental approach produces forms of criminal procedure that can shock Americans. Continental trial in particular often seems to American observers to operate on a disturbing de facto presumption of guilt; the most recent example is the high-profile trial of Amanda Knox. Yet the continental approach has contributed to the making of a significantly more humane criminal justice system than ours. Moreover, the continental approach is better suited to cope with the rise of new forms of scientific investigation. The Article pleads for a shift away from the American culture of rights for the innocent toward a greater concern with continental-style rights for the guilty. It closes with an Appendix assessing the Knox case.
Click here to download this article
American criminal law has a deep commitment to the presumption of innocence. Yet at the same time, American criminal justice is, by international standards, extraordinarily harsh. This Article addresses this troubling state of affairs. The Article contrasts the American approach with the approach of the inquisitorial tradition of continental Europe. Inquisitorial justice, it argues, has a less far-reaching presumption of innocence than American justice does. Yet if continental justice puts less weight on the rights of the innocent it puts more on the rights of the guilty: While its presumption of innocence is comparatively weaker, it has what can be called a strong presumption of mercy. The continental approach produces forms of criminal procedure that can shock Americans. Continental trial in particular often seems to American observers to operate on a disturbing de facto presumption of guilt; the most recent example is the high-profile trial of Amanda Knox. Yet the continental approach has contributed to the making of a significantly more humane criminal justice system than ours. Moreover, the continental approach is better suited to cope with the rise of new forms of scientific investigation. The Article pleads for a shift away from the American culture of rights for the innocent toward a greater concern with continental-style rights for the guilty. It closes with an Appendix assessing the Knox case.
Click here to download this article
15 April 2015
Social Death as a Way of Punishing and Preventing Mass Murder
Tuesday, March 24th,
2015: the crash of the Airbus A320, Flight Germanwings 9525 from Barcelona to Düsseldorf.
Because he is aware of the fact that his depressive state and his eye condition
will over time cause the loss of his job as a pilot for the subsidiary of a
prestigious airline, and realizing that his dream of becoming an aircraft
captain on intercontinental flights is doomed to failure, a young copilot chose
to end his life, leading 149 other people to death. According to the Marseilles
prosecutor’s narrative, the facts speak for themselves: the crime was
premeditated. The perpetrator took advantage of the captain’s brief absence to lock him out the
cockpit, cut off any form of communication with the outside, and operate a
progressive descent, which about ten minutes later would crash the aircraft on the
slopes of the French Alps, causing the death of all passengers and crew
members.
Such a despicable crime defies comprehension. One cannot use the term terrorism, even though the act triggers fear, since there is no ideological or political aim. Although such mass murder is heinous and inhuman, it cannot be considered as a crime against humanity without political, philosophical, racial, or religious motives.
Yet such a crime is a denial of humanity, not only of one person, but of a large number of victims who were, with a few exceptions, anonymous and had nothing to do with the perpetrator’s frustrating life experience or the organization on which he cast blame.
Whether domestic or
international, criminal law does not provide any specific characterization for this
kind of crime, though increasingly frequent. The perpetrator knows his act will
have global significance and visibility due to media and social network coverage.
More and more anti-heroes kill dozens of people, often randomly, before killing
themselves, whether in shootings in schools, universities, shopping malls or
other public areas or, such as in the present case, through the destruction of
an aircraft and the killing of all those on board.
Such acts challenge our ability to react. Efforts are made to secure public places; companies and regulatory authorities will revise air transport security protocols, but criminal law cannot have any effect on the criminal who kills himself in the process.
We are left with the
resource of punishing the criminal by depriving him of the posthumous fame he was
longing for.
Pictures of this young man smiling in front of the Golden Gate Bridge or wearing glittering sportswear have been shown all around the world. They ensure the triumph of the diabolical ego of potential mass murderers and are an insult to the families of the victims. Let us punish such odious beings using one of the harshest sanctions the social group can inflict, a total and absolute anonymous treatment. May his face be concealed with black on any video or photographic representation, may his name be ignored forever. In the past, France used to inflict the sentence of “civil death,” a sanction that until 1854 would treat convicts serving a life sentence as dead. Though physically alive, the convict was treated as dead, losing legal personality and all its attributes. Let us impose the sentence of “social death,” by no longer recognizing as human those denying our humanity.
If the media and the
people relaying the pictures acted this way, we may perhaps defeat plans of
other frustrated people who may find less incentive in playing the anti-heroes and
causing collective death.
Furthermore, such
anonymous treatment would help protect the family, friends, and neighbors of
the murderer, whose lives are shattered and made unbearable due to journalistic
interference, collective stigmatization, and what must be feelings of overwhelming
personal guilt by virtue of their relationship with the murderer.
The idea is not to
promote silence when dealing with those terrible events, which obviously have
to be discussed. The point is to deprive the murderer of his name and face, to
make him sink into his fate of anonymous cursed copilot. Since his crime is
unspeakable, we should deprive him of his name and identity; he should become
void, as one who has never existed. Not even a stone should bear his name.
There is no need to amend any law or draft international agreements to do so. Let us act as responsible citizens by changing the law through our collective behavior, which may become a national and international custom. Custom is a way of reclaiming the law where our representatives are slow or powerless in making it evolve. Let us create a usage or common practice of treating collective murderers anonymously, so that neither our contemporaries, nor our descendants will be able to know, or even care to know, the name or the face of those who despise and hate mankind. Some newspapers and television channels already do so. Such behavior must be promoted and generalized. We do not want to allow our contemporaries to make a gruesome connection between happiness and horror; we want to prevent our children from portraying the denial of mankind with smile and innocence.
© 2015 Olivier Moréteau,
translated from the French by Sara Vono, with the help of Jennifer Lane and
Marie-Antoinette Moréteau.
See original in French on Le juriste français
14 April 2015
BOOK: Amaya on the Nature of Coherence and its Role in Legal Argument
Hart Publishing has recently published Amalia Amaya's The Tapestry of Reason: An Inquiry into the Nature of Coherence and its Role in Legal Argument. The abstract reads:
Recently legal scholarship has been heavily influenced by coherence theories of law and adjudication. These theories significantly advance the case for coherentism in law, yet a number of problems remain. This ambitious new work is the first to develop a coherence-based theory of legal reasoning, and in so doing address, or at least mitigate, these problems. The book is organised in three parts. Part one critically analyses the main coherentist approaches to both normative and factual reasoning in law. Part two investigates coherence theory in a number of fields that are relevant to law: coherence theories of epistemic justification, coherentist approaches to belief revision and theory-choice, coherence theories of practical and moral reasoning and coherence-based approaches to discourse interpretation. Taking this interdisciplinary analysis as a starting point, part three develops a coherence-based model of legal reasoning, building upon the standard theory of legal reasoning, leading to a reconsideration of some of the basic assumptions that characterise this theory and suggesting some lines along which it may be further developed. Thus, the book not only improves upon the current state of coherence theory in law, but also helps to articulate a theory of legal reasoning that results in better decision-making.
THE
AUTHOR
Amalia
Amaya is a
Researcher in the Institute of Philosophical Research at the National
Autonomous University of Mexico.
BOOK
DETAILS
March
2015 9781849460705 560pp Hbk RSP: £75
/ US$150
Discount Price: £60 / US$120
UK, EU
and ROW: http://www.hartpub.co.uk/BookDetails.aspx?ISBN=9781849460705
13 April 2015
WEBSITE (New!): The International Academy of Comparative Law
The International Academy of Comparative Law has a new, engaging website.
Have a look at http://iuscomparatum.info/!!
Have a look at http://iuscomparatum.info/!!
Subscribe to:
Posts (Atom)